Translate

Monday, 8 September 2025

On Tragedy and Madness

 Tragedy and Madness

The deepest yet most common meaning underlying the words

‘tragedy’ and ‘tragic’ is that events so described are those which

challenge one's reason for or belief in living. The questioning of

existence and of meaning is an inevitable response to disaster and a

constant feature of tragedy. Frequently (and, in fact, it is the accepted

logic of most clichés on the subject), the outcome of an overwhelming

personal catastrophe is mental breakdown. The air-plane crash, the

natural disaster, the genocidal massacre, the assassination, the

maternal infanticide--all are rightly described as "tragic" in so far as

they have the potential to throw out of contention the conviction that

existence is reasonable and significant, and thereby imply or promote

aberrant behaviour or perceptions. This intuitive and logical

connection between what is "tragic" and what is "mad" is, I believe, a

key feature of those dramas we typically call tragedies.


Primitive ritual vs alienation

Despite this potential correlation, forthright treatment of the

relationship between tragedy and madness is rare in the literature of

both psychology and literary criticism. One exception to this

tendency is Ralph J. Hallman's The Psychology of Literature: A

Study of Alienation and Tragedy. Hallman adopts what might be

described as a psycho-anthropological approach to tragedy. He

argues that the origin of tragedy lies in the collision of primitive

rituals which, through the enactment of death and rebirth, were

psychically sustaining, and rationality, which alienated the individual

from this psychological sustenance. Primitive ritual underlines the

positive sense, the rejuvenation, of death leading to rebirth; rationality

discredits this vision, and pre-empts the immediacy and spontaneity,

and the sense of community and self affirmation brought about by the

ritual. Tragedy expresses the general sense of alienation inherent in

this situation. It re-enacts the atavistic desire to die as a means of

recapturing life's spontaneity and, at the same time, its rationality

invalidates this death. Rationality furthers the alienation it has

engendered because it fails to revivify the sense of self as ritual had

done. Hallman writes:


. . . the great tragedies re-enact this death drama--its necessity

and meaninglessness; they depict the alienation of man, and

because man's rational faculty establishes the alienating

conditions, tragedy depicts the bankruptcy of intelligence as a

measure which one must take in vain effort to escape the final

estrangement. 1

In Hallman's view "alienation" and "estrangement" are inevitable to

tragedy.


Tragedy signifies man's failure to achieve identity; it traces out

his efforts to discover who he is and what he ought to do and

how he fits into the general scheme of things. In the broadest

sense tragedy reports the failure of personality formation and

consequently installs those conditions which destroy the values

which are normally associated with individual personality. 2

 

Madness in Ancient Literature

While many studies note the presence of madness in tragedy, few
explicitly acknowledge or extensively consider a basic connection
between tragedy and the breakdown of personality as Hallman has
done. In Madness in Ancient Literature, Ainsworth O'Brien-Moore
catalogues examples of madness from the tragedies of Aeschylus,
Sophocles and Euripides, and distinguishes each of the dramatists'
treatment of madness, but he reaches no conclusions about the
relationship between madness and tragedy.


Mind and Madness in Ancient Greece

More promising is Bennett Simon's Mind and Madness in Ancient

Greece in which he confirms that "tragedy reveals a great interest in

madness, which it shows as arising from a matrix of deep ambivalence

and unbearable conflict." 3 "The heroes of tragedy who go mad,"

Simon observes, "do so when their world is collapsing around them.

Their madness is part of a frantic attempt to hold on to what they

know and think right. Their world involves issues of state, the gods,

the family, and the microcosm of their own conflicted ideals and

passions." 4 Simon's comments are only intended to describe

madness as it is portrayed in ancient drama but, as my forthcoming

argument will reveal, the terms of his description are tantamount to a

definition of tragedy.


Madness in Shakespearean Tragedy

H. Somerville broaches this insight in his book, Madness in

Shakespearean Tragedy, when he points out that in tragedy, "in the

case of an insane character it may well be asked: Is the catastrophe in

his death or in his madness?" 5 However, Dr. Somerville retreats

from any further consideration of a link between tragedy and madness,

choosing instead to "explain some of the difficulties occurring in the

speeches, as well as those arising out of the strange and puzzling

behaviour of the principal characters during their attacks of insanity."6


The Mad Folk of Shakespeare

J.C. Bucknill, in his book, The Mad Folk of Shakespeare, published

in 1867, observes that "abnormal states of mind were a favorite

study of Shakespeare." 7 However, Bucknill does not specifically

align madness with tragedy.


The Birth of Tragedy

In fact, the intuition of a connection between tragedy and madness,

it might be argued, is distinctly modern and has only come to us since

Nietzsche. Prior to The Birth of Tragedy we find little connection

between tragedy and madness in the critical analyses of tragedy. The

absence of this recognition, I would contend, is due not to the lack of

episodes of madness in extant tragedies, nor to the analysts' failure to

note them, but to the dominance of idealist or systemic approaches to

tragedy which automatically made madness a low priority or even an

extraneous feature of tragedy.


Aristotle's Poetics

Gerald Else in his introduction to Aristotle Poetics notes the paucity

of discussion of "poetic madness" or "inspiration" in the Poetics

despite this phenomenon having been frequently discussed by Plato.

Whatever the reason (and to my notion the status of poetic

Inspiration had been oblique and precarious even in Plato's

thinking), Aristotle does not in fact make any significant use of

the idea. There is one passing reference to poetic madness, in

section 17; but however interpreted, it clearly does not belong

to the main structure of Aristotle's theory. 8

If we consider section 17 on the "Essential procedures in converting a

plot into a play," we find Aristotle's argument for realistic portrayals of

passion.

Also one should work the appropriate figures and forms of

speech into the text, as far as possible. For people in the grip of

passions are most persuasive because they share the natural

tendencies we have, and it is the man who conveys dejection or

rages with anger in the most natural terms who makes us feel

dejection or anger. (Hence the composition is an affair of either the wellendowed

or the manic individual; for of these two types the

ones are impressionable while the others are liable to be

"possessed" from time to time.) 9

Clearly, high passion is part of Aristotle's understanding of tragedy--he

makes "fear and pity" the center of his definition and he considers one

of the "better" forms of anagnorisis that which carries "a shattering

emotional effect" 10 --yet madness, in his analysis, remains an

extraneous or ornamental aspect of tragedy. For example, still in

section 17, Aristotle suggests that in constructing a tragedy, first the

plot should be outlined, then the characters' names and "other" scenes

should be added. Aristotle includes the madness of Orestes as an

example of one of these "other" scenes. While these affective and

even passionate elements are present in Aristotle's vision of tragedy,

they must eventually be subordinated to his sense of the higher order

of rationalism.


Hegel on Tragedy

Hegel, like Aristotle, submits tragedy to the tyranny of the "Idea."

Hegel's typical tragedy is the case of a hero who becomes totally

identified with a principle, an idea, a commitment, who then finds

himself in an "unmediated contradiction" between his principles and

his concern for a loved-one, which eventually destroys him. In Hegel's

analysis, as in Aristotle's, we can see the possibility of madness being

a feature of tragedy; however, both these philosophers attach tragedy

to a larger, absolutist vision of the universe, which reduces the here-and-

now world of the tragic hero, and his psychological conflicts, to

incidents which are valued only in so far as they reflect or symbolize

the idealized universe.


The Dionysian and Schopenhauer

In The Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche sets out with the intention of

avoiding the theodicies of his predecessors. He creates a new

category of concern, "the Dionysian," in which the sensuous, the

immediate, the communal, abandon, frenzy, intoxication, ecstasy and

madness are upheld and valued in counterbalance to the "Apollonian"

values of form, discipline and control. However, in his conclusion

that the tragic hero abandons individuality and plunges himself into

the primordial will Nietzsche surrenders his argument to

Schopenhauer's theodicy of the will and returns madness to mysticism.

Nonetheless, Nietzsche's discussion of tragedy so unbalanced all

previous approaches to tragedy that tragedy could never again be

spoken of in the same way. Refined discussions of dulce and utile now

seem feeble, the great Wheel of Fortune appears little more than a

quaint metaphor, and madness itself, through Nietzsche, has arguably

become the positive value of tragedy. What we find in the modern age

are not simply new definitions of tragedy but new ways of defining it.

Consistent in these myriad approaches to tragedy is the intimation of

madness or at least the conditions of madness as definitive of what is

tragic.


Tragedy and Tragic Vision

In Tragedy and Tragic Vision , Murray Krieger describes tragedy

and the modern world as linked by "tragic vision" but separated by the

mitigating aesthetic form of traditional tragedy and the unrelieved

tragic vision of the modern age. Yet madness, in his assessment, is

implied to exist in both traditional tragedy and in the literature of

"tragic vision." For example, Krieger describes the evolution of tragic

vision as follows:

. . the tragic vision was born inside tragedy, as a part of it: as a

possession of the tragic hero, the vision was a reflection in the

realm of thematics of the fully fashioned aesthetic totality

which was tragedy. But fearful and even demonic in its

revelations, the vision needed the ultimate soothing power of

the aesthetic form which contained it--of tragedy itself--in order

to preserve for the world a sanity which the vision itself denied.

11


We should recognize that Krieger's polarization of the traditional

form called "tragedy" and the modern theme called "tragic vision" is

based on the assumption that the aesthetic form of tragedy asserts a

resolution of harmony, a return to an ordered universe, and the

reaffirmation of a transcendent moral order. Krieger describes the

modern "unrelieved tragic vision" as follows:


. . . in its seizing upon the particular and its denial of any

totality it is an heretical vision; and in its defiance of all rational

moral order it is a demoniac vision. Finally, in a very special

sense it is a casuistic vision; and it is this characteristic,

perhaps, that makes it especially accessible to literary portrayal.

The tragic vision, a product of crisis and of shock, is an

expression of man only in an extreme situation, never in a

normal or routine one. Literature dealing with it frequently

dwells on the exceptional man; and when it does choose a

normal man it does so only to convert him, by way of the

extremity he lives through, into the exceptional man. 12

The paradox of tragedy is that it presents madness, chaos and the

demise of humanity yet, at the same time, tragedy as an aesthetic form

remains sane, ordered, and exalting of humanity and human passions.

This paradox is an unavoidable fact of tragedy, as true for the

American tragedians of the 1940's as it was for the Greeks of the 5th

century BC. Unmitigated tragic vision is a logical impossibility.

Tragic vision is always mitigated, in fact, contradicted by the fact that

it is found within an aesthetic form. On the other side of his

argument, Krieger overstates the case for the catharsis of traditional

tragedy achieved through aesthetic form and the restoration of the

morally ordered universe. When I consider Creon and Lear and Willy

Loman, I find little difference in the degree to which these men are

lost and equally little in their life experiences to offset the pathos

which their destinies engender. When I consider Oedipus and

Macbeth and Hedda Gabler, I find little indication in the plays of

mitigation of their catastrophic destinies except the plays themselves

as aesthetic forms, and this is true in each of the three cases.


Tragedy Is Not Enough

In Karl Jasper's Tragedy Is Not Enough we find the merging of

existential and transcendental visions of tragedy and, I would contend,

an implicit argument for madness as the common denominator of

both. Like Steiner, Jaspers insists upon transcendence as being

essential to tragedy, but Jaspers offers a much broader notion of

transcendence, and invites the conclusion that mental breakdown

precipitates transcendence. Jaspers argues that "breakdown and

failure reveal the true nature of things." 1 As he involves himself in

the tragic, "man's mind fails and breaks down in the very wealth of its

potentialities." 2 This breakdown automatically implies

transcendence.

Both the exceptional man and the sublime order have their own

limits, beyond which they break down. What conquers in

tragedy is the transcendent--or rather even this does not

conquer, for it makes itself felt only through the whole

situation. It neither dominates nor submits; it simply exists. 15

Anatomy of Criticism

Though not explicitly stated, intimations of madness seem to hover

about tragedy even in Northrop Frye's "scientific" study of literature,

Anatomy of Criticism. Frye basically attempts to make tragedy a

mere category to be subsumed under a pseudo-scientific

superstructure. The shortcoming of a structuralist approach is that,

while it may place tragedy coherently within the body of literature and

art, it tells us little about the meaning and value of tragedy. The

structuralist tendency is to forgo the question of tragedy's

correspondence to life in order to maintain the internal coherence of a

theory. This, however, is not to deny that insight can be gained from

the comparison of tragedy to comedy or epic or satire. For example,

Frye's discussion of the "tragic mode" fuels our present hypothesis:

“. . . there is a general distinction between fictions in which the hero

becomes isolated from his society, and fictions in which he is

incorporated into it. This distinction is expressed by the words ‘tragic’

and ‘comic’ . . . .” 16 Though Frye's notion of the tragic touches upon

alienation, his vision of tragedy in "The Mythos of Autumn" is

inconclusive as to a connection between tragedy and madness.


Modern Tragedy

Raymond Williams' approach to tragedy in Modern Tragedy is

historical; that is, he sees tragedy not as fixed but as an experience that

is rediscovered within new circumstances and conventions. When

Williams comes to describe what he calls "liberal tragedy," which

extends roughly from Marlowe and Shakespeare to Ibsen and Miller,

he writes:

Much of the new drama, even when its reference points are

familiar categories, takes its most active life from a

consciousness of the self in a passing moment of experience: a

self-consciousness which is now in itself dramatic, and which

new dramatic resources are employed to express. The common

process of life is seen at its most intense in an individual

experience.

Tragedy, according to Williams, is now rooted in "the nature of a

particular man" and the process by which he discovers his external

limits.

But the limits men reach, in their challenge to order, are not

only of this kind. There are new limits, within man himself.

Order can break there, within the personality, as decisively and

as tragically. Breakdown and madness, as private experiences,

are quite newly realised and explored. The emphasis, as we

take the full weight, is not on the naming of limits, but on their

intense and confused discovery and exploration. 17

Williams has, of course, repositioned the dividing line between

modern and traditional tragedy. From our present perspective we must

ask of William's dividing line: Is there really such a difference

between Orestes' "public" madness and Hamlet's "private" madness?

Is there such a difference in the way Creon's world falls apart and the

way Lear's world falls apart? Furthermore, can we separate a man's

discovery of his external limits from his discovery of his internal

limits? Are the two not inseparably intertwined? Are they not, in

fact, one? For example, isn't Oedipus's discovery of the fate the gods

have in store for him, in fact, a collision with his own internal limits,

just as Willy Loman's bumping into the limits of the American dream

is for him an internal crisis? In other words, if we bridge Williams'

historical distinctions, tragedy appears as the consistent experience of

reaching one's limits and the consequent breakdown of one's sense of

order and self.


In Summary

Despite the variety of these approaches we should recognize that

madness, though never focused on, remains an implicit element of

tragedy. In the formalist approach of Aristotle we discover the

"passion," the "shock," and "the shattering emotional effect" of

tragedy; in the idealist aesthetics of Hegel we hear of the unresolvable

contradiction which destroys the individual; in Nietzsche's Dionysian

approach we learn of the necessary destruction of individuation. In

Krieger's analysis the tragic hero becomes an existential visionary

compelled to see beyond sanity. In Jasper's melange of secular

existentialism and religious transcendentalism, the destruction of the

individual mind is again predicated by tragedy. Even Frye's

mythopoeic structuralism concedes the alienation inherent in tragedy.

And, as we have just seen, Williams' historical/cultural analysis

places madness at the middle point of our history of tragedy.

Yet having confirmed the presence of madness or the etiology of

madness in this variety of approaches to tragedy, we are left with little

assurance of a shared understanding of tragedy itself. Not only does

each of these critics employ a different methodology but the

methodology is in turn applied to different bodies of literature. It is

perhaps this critical Tower-of-Babel situation which compelled Oscar

Mandel to write A Definition of Tragedy. Hard definitions of tragedy

are a rarity in recent times. 18


A Definition of Tragedy

In A Definition of Tragedy, Mandel confronts the existential

visionaries and traditional formalists with a direct and definitive

approach to tragedy. Mandel rejects both the "tragic vision" of

modern existentialists and the theodicies of Hegel and Schiller. He

also dismisses inward looking structures such as those developed by

Northrop Frye in his Anatomy of Criticism. Mandel's argument

against ethical and existential interpretations of tragedy is "the

anarchy of subjective and historical interpretation" which they

impose.19 His refutation of structuralist categorizations is that a

definition of tragedy "is acceptable only on condition of being in

some manner true to the world which supplies it with materials." 20

Mandel offers the following definition:

A work of art is tragic if it substantiates the following

situation: A protagonist who commands our earnest good will

is impelled in a given world by a purpose, or undertakes an

action, of a certain seriousness and magnitude; and by that very

purpose or action, subject to that same given world, necessarily

and inevitably meets with grave spiritual or physical suffering.

21

In the defence of his definition Mandel argues against catharsis ,

anagnorisis , and "nobility" being essential to tragedy. As well,

Mandel, like Aristotle and Frye, focuses on the fact that tragedy

describes "a situation." However, as Mandel is quick to point out

himself, the book is more about definitions than about tragedy. Even

if we were to accept this legalistic definition, we would be at a loss to

determine what it tells us about tragedy.


Tragedy in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy

At this point we should rightly ask: if, as Mandel contends, these

various formal, traditional, transcendental, existential, and structuralist

theories have proven inadequate, is any theory of tragedy definitive?

For that matter, is it possible to derive or deduce a final formulation

for tragedy? At this point in the long history of literature and of

literary criticism a final definition of tragedy seems beyond the

possibility of consensus. As Morris Weitz points out in his article,

"Tragedy," in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, given the divergence

of artifacts and opinions, it is not possible to determine "a set of

necessary and sufficient properties" which account for the concept of

tragedy. Nor is it possible, as Weitz indicates, to give the final

definition of a concept like tragedy, when new tragedies may yet be

written which will change our understanding of the concept.

Tragedy is not definable (in the theory sense of true, real

definition) for another reason, namely that its use must allow

for the ever present possibility of new conditions. It is simply a

historical fact that the concept, as we know and use it, has

continuously accommodated new cases of tragedy, and, more

important, the properties of these cases. One cannot state the

necessary and sufficient conditions for the correct use of a

concept whose very use entails the requirement that the concept

be applicable to new conditions. 22

Weitz concludes that

. . . no set of necessary and sufficient properties is common to

all [tragedies]. Nor will further examination of the human

situation furnish us with a theory of tragedy, because there is no

tragic fact in the world about which a theory of tragedy could

be true or which would corroborate such a theory. 23

Weitz contends that when we speak of tragedy, "such discourse is

intelligible." However, I would note that in discussing tragedy

without the benefit of an accepted definition contemporary critics are

forced to limit themselves to defensible topics like "tragic myth" or

"the masks of tragedy" or "themes in tragedy" or "features of tragedy"

while adopting an ostensive definition of the term. The fact that there

is little agreement on a canon of tragedies seems to jeopardize or,

more to the point, trivialize even these arguments. If we compare

Sewall ( The Vision of Tragedy ) and Steiner ( The Death of Tragedy ),

we discover that Sewall's basic tenet is that the essence of tragedy is

the knowledge gained through suffering; whereas Steiner's central

theme is that the core of tragedy is the awareness of transcendence

discovered through suffering. On the surface they present

complementary points of view, but when it comes to the specifics of

individual tragedies they differ widely. Sewall sees the story of Job as

one of the two pillars of the tragic worldview. Steiner, however, is

unequivocal that there is nothing tragic in the story of Job. Sewell

lists Long Day's Journey into Night , The Trial , and Absolon, Absolon

as examples of tragedy. Steiner's thesis is that tragedy ended with the

neo-classical period.


In the absence of a final theory or definition of tragedy or some fact

of life to which tragedy appeals, all statements about tragedy broach

tautology. How can any statement about tragedy be "proven" when a

body of plays must be selected to induce a particular notion of tragedy,

and then the same body of plays must then be used to prove the

validity of the notion?


In any discussion of tragedy, what is at issue is the reasons given for

the use of the term. One theory may compete with another in terms of

erudition, or verisimilitude, or coherence, or its appeal to intuition,

but no theory can claim to correspond to truth. The purpose of such

discussion, then, is merely to inch closer to the truth by adding to

awareness and enlarging understanding. As Weitz points out:

Each theory of tragedy expresses an honorific redefinition of

tragedy that restricts the use of the term to a selection from its

multiple criteria. It is this selection, as a recommendation to

concentrate upon certain preferred criteria or properties of

tragedy that are neglected, distorted, or omitted by other

theories. If we attend to these criteria or properties instead of to

the unsuccessful attempts of essentialist definitions, we shall

have much to learn from the individual theories about what to

look for in tragedies as well as how to look at them. 24

The point of any discussion of tragedy is, therefore, not so much to

prove as to persuade. The purpose of that persuasion is to enhance

understanding, to illuminate new perspectives, to provide insights.

Thus we can now speak of definitions and theories of tragedies from

the comfortable perspective of the shared understanding that absolute

terms are not possible, and that final definitions and ultimate theories

are beyond the hope of consensus. We can therefore take the liberty

of speaking of an understanding rather than the definition of tragedy.

Our goal, then, is to consider eight plays written over three millennia,

each of which has been widely discussed in terms of tragedy, as

portrayals of a process of madness and the insights which that process

reveals.


Notes

1. Ralph J. Hallman, Psychology and Literature (New York:

Philosophical Library, 1961), p. 21.

2. Ibid, p. 15.

3 . B. Simon, Mind and Madness in Ancient Greece (Ithaca: Cornell

University Press, 1978), p.89.

4. Ibid, p. 90.

5. H. Somerville, Madness in Shakespearean Tragedy (London: The

Richards' Press, 1929), p. 14.

6. Ibid, p.15.

7. J.C. Bucknill, The Mad Folk of Shakespeare (New York: Burt

Franklin, 1867), p. xi.

8. G. F. Else, "Introduction," Aristotle Poetics (Ann Arbor: University

of Michigan Press, 1970), p. 5.

9. Ibid, section 17, p. 48.

10. Ibid. See sec. 9. p. 25 for the basic definition, and sec. 15, p. 42 for

the discussion of "the recognition" having "a shattering emotional

effect"--though here, in contradiction to earlier claims, Aristotle seems to

prefer for tragedy to end happily, and in sec. 16, p. 47 he again refers to

the "emotional shock" brought about by probable cause.

11. M. Krieger, "Tragedy and Tragic Vision," Tragedy: Vision and Form, ed., R.W. Corrigan (San Francisco: Chandler, 1965), p. 20. 

12. Ibid, p. 33.

13. K. Jaspers, Tragedy Is Not Enough, trans. H.A.T. Reiche et al

(Boston: Beacon Press, 1952), p. 43.

14. Ibid, p. 42

15. Ibid, pp. 51-2.

16. N. Frye, Anatomy of Criticism (Princeton: Princeton University

Press, 1957), p. 35.

17. R. Williams, Modern Tragedy (Stanford: Stanford University Press,

1966), p.89.

18. G. Brereton offers another example of a "hard definition" in his

Principles of Tragedy (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1968), p. 20

19. O. Mandel, A Definition of Tragedy (New York: New York

University Press, 1961), p. 56.

20. Ibid, p. 56.

21. Ibid, p. 20.

22. M. Weitz, "Tragedy," The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed., P.

Edwards (New York: MacMillan, 1967), p. 160.

23. Ibid, p. 160.

24. Ibid, p. 160.

Why Does Everyone Care So Much about This Huawei Issue?

The Huawei case matters to Canadians I don’t know about “everyone,” but I can tell you why I, as a Canadian, “care so much about the Huawe...